Notes on Subjectivity, Qualia and the Like
Ben Goertzel
July 21, 2005
This
informal document is a continuation of a blog entry I wrote on July 19, 2005,
in which I talked about the “circular containment” relationship between
subjective and objective reality. This
was supposed to be a follow-up blog entry, but it grew beyond the size of a
reasonable blog entry (though it still has the informality and speculative
nature of a blog entry!).
In these
notes, I will present a number of related ideas about subjective and objective
reality, moving further into the domain of consciousness, qualia, and the
like. These ideas are somewhat diverse,
but they lead in a very interesting direction – toward, for example, a possible
way of articulating novel mathematical laws governing the behavior of qualia in
subjective reality.
All this
material is quite speculative and partially-baked, and is posted here in the
spirit of open sharing and exploratory dialogue.
I have not
definitely tried to answer every possible skeptical objection to the ideas
proposed here. I have thought of a
number of arguments people would have with these ideas, and conceived various
counterarguments, but I haven’t taken the time to type in this content.
More on the
Interpenetration of Subjectivity and Objectivity
As I
discussed in the above-mentioned blog entry, starting from the assumption of
subjective reality, one can derive the possibility of some kind of objective
reality emerging – via arguments from developmental psychology. The root of objective reality lies in the
infant’s realization of “object permanence” – that mommy and daddy still exist
when they leave the room, and their hand still has visual properties when they
close their eyes.
We don’t yet
know any way to derive the detailed structure and dynamics of our physical
universe from facts about subjective reality, but my suspicion is that this may
be possible. This gets into deep issues
of “grand unification physics”, specifically John Archibald Wheeler’s idea of
“law without law,” which hypothesizes that the laws of our physical universe
are in some sense optimal, so that if one has an objective or physical world
with unformed, indefinite laws, eventually the laws will settle into the
optimal-law configuration (being the laws of our universe). Wheeler’s idea was to assume some kind of
pre-geometric, pre-lawful universe, and derive the laws of our universe from
this. But the idea makes just as much
(or little ;-) sense if one places subjective reality in the place of Wheeler’s
primordial pre-geometric world.
On the other
hand, starting the assumption of objective reality – and furthermore assuming a
complex, appropriately structured objective reality like our own, with the
capability of the formation of complex, self-organizing systems -- one can
derive the possibility of intelligent systems like humans and AI’s, that will
describe themselves as having subjective realities, and whose internal dynamics
will be conveniently describable using the notion of “subjective reality.”
What these
arguments suggest is that subjective reality may be derived as a pattern in
objective reality (in that the assumption of minds having subjective realities
may help one to explain the dynamics of intelligent systems within objective
reality); and, objective reality may be derived as a pattern in subjective
reality (in that the concept of objective reality arises in a mind as a way of
organizing its subjective percepts/concepts).
Propositional
Reality
An alternate
way to think about these issues is, I suggest, to introduce a third kind of
reality: propositional reality. By this
I simply mean the universe of logical statements, or more properly: logical
statements using a vocabulary of logical atoms that includes a way to indicate
“this” which is assumed understood by both speaker and listener. One can think about both objective and
subjective reality by associating them with subsets of propositional reality.
Propositions
may include, for example, “1+1=2” or “This [indicating a ball] is red” or “This
[indicating the speaker] feels sad” or abstract statements like “Red things
make people and donkeys feel happy”, etc.
One can look
at propositional reality as an abstraction of social reality and linguistic
interaction. All these discussions
about subjective and objective reality that we’re having are basically an
exchange of logical propositions among human minds. This discourse only makes sense if one assumes that there is some
reality to the space of logical propositions.
We can
exchange propositions about things we see around us – so objective reality, in
this context, boils down to a set of propositions that all or most of the
participants in the dialogue can agree on.
We can also
exchange propositions about our internal, subjective worlds – for instance, I
can string words together evocatively describing a subjective feeling I’ve had,
and you may read my words and map this approximately into some feeling you’ve
had. So subjective content also boils
down to a set of propositions that multiple participants can understand. And in some cases, it boils down to
propositions that multiple participants can agree on, such as “Parting is such
sweet sorrow.”
We can’t say
that “parting is such sweet sorrow” is objectively real in the standard sense,
but we can say that it’s a proposition that is mutually comprehensible to
members of a proposition-exchanging community, and that appears to very many of
these individuals to be true.
This example
shows that one of the main things distinguishing objective from subjective
reality is that the former consists of propositions that nearly everyone in the
dialogic community agrees to be true.
Nothing in subjective reality elicits such widespread agreement. “Parting is such sweet sorrow” may be widely
agreed on, but not quite as widely as “This rock is hard.”
In this
context, the circular-containment relationship between objective and subjective
reality boils down basically to mutual logical derivability. If we take a large enough set of
propositions about an individual’s subjective world, then through some complex
derivations we should be able to derive important propositions about objective
reality – and vice versa. However,
these derivations may be long and complex.
We may view subjective and objective reality as “islands” in
proposition-space, separated by long and difficult chains of derivation.
The
propositional point of view certainly has its shortcomings – one may argue that
projecting into the space of propositions loses something of the essence of
both objective and subjective reality.
However, this is exactly the kind of projection we make when we discuss
these matters via intellectual discourse like this one. (Though of course, sharing propositions is
not the only way for humans to share knowledge: there is wordless transmission
of feeling and intuition, and there is purely physical interaction in the
context of the objective world.)
One reason I
like the propositional reality idea is that it places the idea of scientific
validation in a proper (i.e. sociological) perspective. Some people like to say that objective
reality is somehow more real than subjective reality because statements about
objective reality can be scientifically validated. But what does the scientific method really come down to, in
practice? It’s a complex thing (which
I’ve addressed in an extended essay on the philosophy of science, written last
year and posted on www.goertzel.org/dynapsyc), but part of it has to do with
the replication of experimental results by different experimenters. In other words, it has to do with the
formulation of propositions that multiple individuals will agree are true. In this sense scientific validation is not
really so different from the creation of agreeable abstractions regarding subjective
experience.
The Problem
of Qualia
Related to
the above issues, I've been thinking hard about how to get around the
"problem of qualia" in the philosophy of mind.
Let me first
explain what I think the problem is.
First of
all, a "quale" is defined (by dictionary.com) as "a property,
such as whiteness, considered independently from things having the
property." In discussions of
consciousness, the term is normally used to refer to something that is
perceived by a conscious, feeling, aware mind – as opposed to something that is
conceived as having an absolute existence in an objective world. We experience the whiteness of the wall
(this is a quale); but we, as subjectively experiencing minds, infer the "objective"
existence of the wall, via recognizing patterns of relationship among multiple
qualia.
So what is
the problem of qualia?
Sociologically,
the problem is that there are two very distinct camps out there.
Some of us
think "qualia" is a meaningful concept, and that it makes sense to
think in terms of things like "Ben's subjective experience of
whiteness."
Others
believe that "qualia" is a nonsensical conceptual construction. They make arguments like "The whole
idea of qualia is meaningless, because I can never measure a brain and tell if
there are qualia in there or not."
Or: "Not being George Bush myself, how could I ever tell the
difference between George Bush, and a version of George Bush that had no
qualia?"
How can we
reconcile these two perspectives?
This
sociological distinction reflects a basic conceptual problem, which may be cast
as a linguistic problem: How can we meaningfully connect the language of
subjective experiences (which we all use on an everyday basis) with the
language of empirical observations?
Clearly
there is a connection, because when I say "I experience that tree as
tall", one can then go measure the tree and see if it's tall or not. So, from a subjective point of view, I can
detect correlations between my qualia and scientific measurements. But, from a scientific point of view, I can
never detect such correlations because there is no such thing as a
quale-ometer. I can detect correlations
like "There is a link between a tree being tall and people saying they
have the experience of perceiving the tree as being tall." But this kind of correlation introduces an
unsatisfying level of indirection: one is then dealing with talking rather than
with experiencing directly -- one is dodging the qualia problem rather than
confronting it.
I think the
quale-skeptics are correct that qualia are not measurable. However, I don’t think this means “qualia”
are a meaningless concept. I will give
two examples now to explain the sense in which I think non-measurable entities
can be very meaningful.
The first
example is one that I’ll pursue a little later in these notes: quantum phenomena. Quantum reality contains many phenomena that are known to be
unmeasurable, but that scientists still find very useful to talk about. Because positing and analyzing these
particular unmeasurables proves very useful for explaining various measurable
results.
The second
example is simpler: time. How can we
prove time exists? We can’t. The statement that time exists is not a
falsifiable hypothesis, because the very concept of doing a scientific
experiment involves the notion of time (how can we talk about “replication” of
experiments without assuming the existence of time?). Similarly, I suggest, the statement that qualia exist is not a
falsifiable hypothesis, but the very concept of doing a scientific experiment
involves qualia: we only accept the results of an experiment if we experience
them ourselves. “Seeing is believing”
basically means that we want to observe the outcome of an experiment on a
measuring instrument, in order to definitively accept it. In short, individual experience, like time,
is part of the language that is used to define scientific experimentation, rather
than something that can be measured via scientific experimentation. Asking “can the existence of qualia be
scientifically verified?”, like asking “can the existence of time be
scientifically verified?”, is making a category error.
But as with
time and quantum reality, the concept of qualia can be judged in a human sense
via its usefulness. Is the concept good
at producing interesting, surprising, valuable, ideas? (And, a careful analysis of the history and philosophy
of science reveals that this is ultimately the way scientific research programmes
are validated anyway.)
I’d say the
jury is still out on qualia. They are
very useful as a way of explaining various aspects of human experience – for instance,
I wouldn’t want to try to describe an LSD trip or a meditative experience or a
love affair without referring to various aspects of qualia. On the other hand, they’ve proved less
useful so far for explaining aspects of human cognition. But I tend to suspect that is because the
theory of qualia (in contrast to e.g. the theory of quantum phenomena) has been
extremely poorly developed. With this
in mind, in the second half of these notes, I will sketch some ideas indicating
what I think some aspects of a theory of qualia might look like. Of course, this is a very big topic and I’ll
barely scratch the surface here – in fact I have a lot more thoughts in this
direction, which I don’t have time to write down at the moment.
I note in
passing that Buddhist psychology has a lot to say about the nature of -- but
its vocabulary is obscure and tends to tangle up descriptive ideas with
normative ones. I have been
conceptually inspired by Buddhist psychology in my thinking on these topics,
but I prefer to take a fresh start and introduce a new vocabulary and set of
concepts more closely tied to cognitive science than Eastern religion.
Qualia and
their Properties
OK, so … suppose
“qualia” exist in some meaningful sense, then what else can we say about
them? What general propositions can be
made about this “subjectivity-reflecting propositional content”?
First, a
comment about networks of qualia. When
thinking about qualia like "whiteness", it's hard to see how it could
ever be possible to infer things like walls, trees, electrons and people from
qualia. But the trick is that qualia
like "whiteness" are not the only kind -- there are also more
abstract properties. There are
properties of relationship, such as "on-ness",
"beside-ness" and so forth.
One can experience beside-ness, independently from the things that are
beside each other. This is the quale of
besideness. But then one can piece the
beside-ness together with the things that are beside each other, which is a
matter of building networks of relationship among qualia.
This --
networks of relationships among qualia -- is what the subjective world is made
of.
As noted
above, from a subjective perspective, there is no such thing as a "quale
versus a non-quale." Every
subjective entity has a quale aspect -- it's "being-in-and-of-itself"
-- but then subjective entities may also have relational aspects as well (e.g.
whiteness vs. whiteness-of-the-table, where "table" itself is a
network of relationships among qualia; or besideness vs. besideness of
whiteness and blackness, or besideness of the white wall and the black table).
Qualia,
which are properties, can themselves have properties. For instance, some important properties of qualia are the ones I
call arity, centrality, intensity, solidity and historicity.
Arity has to
do with whether a quale is applicable to one thing ("whiteness") or
two things ("besideness") or more ("give-ness" relates
three things). Qualia with different
arities have different subjective feels to them. Qualia of arity one may be called "elementary"; those
of higher arity may be called "relational."
Centrality
has to do with how much focus is on a given quale. Some things seem to be at the fringe of awareness -- say, a vague
sense of unease or confusion, or an idea that one can sense forming but doesn't
quite grasp yet. Other things are right
at the center of awareness.
Intensity
has to do with how vivid a quale is, how much attention it demands. This is different from centrality --
because, for instance, sometimes the center of one's awareness can be occupied
with something quite pale and calm, other times by something exciting and
demanding-of-attention.
Solidity has
to do with, for example, the difference between qualia that appear to be
perceived and those that appear to be imagined. A tree in the outside world has a different "feel" to
it than a tree imagined inside the mind.
This is not a matter of intensity or centrality; it's a different
dimension. Normally non-solid qualia
have less detail to them than solid qualia but this is not a hard-and-fast
rule.
Relationship
qualia can connect qualia with different degrees of solidity. For instance, if I believe there is (in
objective reality) a fly behind my computer monitor, but I can't see the fly
(only the monitor), then I can experience the (somewhat solid) relationship
between the non-solid quale of the imagined fly and the solid quale of the
perceived monitor.
Finally,
historicity has to do with time -- with, basically, with whether the quale has
ever been Present or not. This quality
gives us our innate sense of whether a quale is a memory or not.
There are
empirical laws relating qualities of qualia; for instance, central qualia tend
to be more intense than peripheral ones, but this is not a universal law. One may distinguish and analyze those
contexts in which peripheral qualia become unusually intense.
Building
objective reality from subjective has to do (in a “proposition space”
framework) with the formation of hypothetical relationships. The blackness of the fly behind the monitor
is not directly experienced as a solid quale, but the hypothesis is made that
if I were to get up and look in back of the monitor, I would then experience it
as a solid quale. Now, getting up to
look in back of the monitor itself involves a bunch of different qualia,
including plenty of relational ones -- so the hypothesis of the fly behind the
monitor is basically a set of implications of the form "If these qualia,
then those qualia." Once the
ability for this kind of abstract implication emerges in a mind, then the
capability to construct a working concept of "objective reality" is
there. Specifically, objective reality
has to do with abstract implications whose conclusions involve solid,
elementary qualia.
These
various descriptors of qualia are somewhat useful for discussing the standard
“paradoxes” of conscious experience.
For instance, Tennessee Leuwenberg, on the SL4 list, recently told the
parable:
"
An
intelligent scientist in the future is born on, and living in a spaceship. The
inside of the spaceship is not devoid of light, but the colouring of all the
internal surfaces happens to be black-and-white in appearance. However, she has
a huge amount of information about physics. In this experiment, she is not
capable of reproducing anything that is coloured for her to see, but she is
able intellectually to fully understand the nature of light, its effects on the
human eyeball, brain, nervous system etc.
One day she
lands on Earth at the end of her mission. Upon opening the hatch, she casts her
eyes first on an enormous bunch of red roses which have been given to her.
‘Oh’, she
says, ‘so that's what it's like’.
“
(Similar
parables have been told by others before, and exist in the philosophy
literature; I just mention this one because I recently heard it.)
Tennessee
then asked: “Has she learnt anything new about colour? If you accept that she
has, then qualia must be real, because she already knew everything that science
could inform her about the world and about colour. There must, therefore, be
something real about colour which is not addressed by science.”
The
difference here seems to be between elementary and abstract qualia, and between
solid and non-solid ones. The scientist
in the spaceship could understand roses using abstract, non-solid qualia. Once on Earth, she could understand them
using elementary, solid qualia. The key
point of this story, then, in terms of the current approach, is that qualia are
differentiated by (among other qualities) arity and solidity.
Quantum
Reality, Subjective Reality, and Exotic Probabilities
Next – going
much further out on a limb, but also generating more original and interesting
speculations -- I will argue that there are fairly interesting analogies to be
built as follows:
Analogy 1
[objective-reality-centric]:
Objective
reality is to subjective reality, roughly as classical-physics reality is to
quantum-physics reality
Rationale:
In both
cases, the latter contain phenomena that are more “nebulous” than the
measurable phenomena in the former, but are still useful for explaining
phenomena in the former.
Analogy 2
[subjective-reality-centric]:
Objective
reality is to subjective reality, roughly as quantum reality is to objective
reality
Rationale:
Objective
reality is built up from subjective reality, and contains things that are not
subjectively real but are useful for explaining things that are subjectively
real. Similarly, quantum reality is
built up from objective reality, and contains things that are not objectively
real but are useful for explaining things that are objectively real.
I will use
these analogies to motivate a novel and interesting hypothesis regarding the
nature of entities within subjective reality.
Please note,
I am not claiming that subjective reality is quantum reality. That would be silly. I'm just making analogies. These analogies are conceptually evocative,
and also seems to lead in some interesting mathematical directions.
First I need
to say something about the relationship between quantum physics and objective
reality. This is a distinction that I
fudged past in my earlier discussion of objective vs. subjective reality. Objective reality, as I discussed it there,
is about things that we can imagine hypothetically observing if we were in a
different position, a different situation etc.
However, the reality portrayed by quantum physics is a bit different,
because it consists of things that we could never, in principle, observe, no
matter what. I don’t think that it
makes sense to consider in-principle-unmeasurable aspects of the hypothetical
quantum universe as part of “objective reality,” exactly. Rather, these things exist in a different
domain – they “exist” in a different sense.
They exist in the sense that postulating their existence is useful for
explaining things that exist in objective, “classical” reality. This is similar to the sense in which
postulating the existence of things in “objective reality” is useful for
explaining things that exist in subjective reality. From a subjectivist perspective, objective reality is a useful
hypothesis because it helps us explain observed patterns in our qualia, and
quantum reality is a useful hypothesis because it assists objective reality in
this job. This is Analogy 2 listed
above..
Explaining
quantum reality properly seems to involve qualities like "probability
wave" that are meaningless in the classical world. These qualities can never be measured
because as soon as they come into contact with a measuring instrument, they
"vanish" -- quantum laws only work for unmeasured entities! So we can, if we like, say that all these
unmeasurable quantum properties are not "real." That's fine, but they're still very useful
for explaining the results of measuring devices. Just as the ball that’s rolled behind the chair is not “real” in
the sense of immediate subjective reality, but is still useful for explaining
the results of immediate subjective observations at other points in time.
Similarly,
subjective reality seems to be reasonably well explicable using qualities like
arity, solidity, centrality, intensity and historicity (and of course, other
qualities that I haven’t explicated here).
These qualities can be measured in various ways (e.g. by asking people
questions, or by doing brain measurements and correlating the results with
peoples' verbal responses) but they also (so I suggest, and I realize this will
be obvious to some people yet controversial to others) seem to have aspects
that can never be measured -- that are not fully captured via verbalization and
are hence, so to speak, beyond the domain of measurement.
This is
Analogy 1 listed above, and it leads up to a very interesting question: What is
the right way to measure and manipulate uncertainty within subjective
reality? In other words, if one has
propositions about subjective reality, and wants to quantify their uncertainty,
what’s the right way to do it?
Cox’s
Theorem shows nicely that “probability” is the right way to handle uncertainty
– but Saul Youssef showed that ordinary real-number probability is not the only
kind of probability there is. One can
construct probabilities obeying all the rest of Cox’s axioms besides
real-number-ness, by using probabilities drawn from any of three other
algebras: the complex numbers, the quaternions or the octonions. Youssef showed that quantum theory can be
derived from the assumption that one should use complex numbers rather than
real numbers to measure uncertainty, together with some other simple
assumptions.
Which leads
up to the very interesting hypothesis that, maybe, subjective reality also calls
for a non-real-number type of probability?
There is
significant intuitive support for this, in the form of the intuition that
subjective reality contains things that are “inexpressible in words” – i.e.
that vanish when crisply expressed in language , in a similar sense to how
quantum uncertainty vanishes when measured by a classical instrument. This kind of intuition is why Amit Goswami
and others have posited that the human unconscious is a quantum system. Goswami ties in this subjectively experienced
uncertainty of the human mind with the hypothesis that the human brain is a
quantum system, but I don’t make this same connection. I think it’s possible the human brain is
a “macroscopic quantum object” in
important senses, but the notion I’m putting forth here is quite different from
that. I’m suggesting that subjective
experience has some of the same mathematical/conceptual properties as quantum
reality, regardless of whether or not the physical system associated with that
subjective experience relies on macroscopic quantum dynamics for its
intelligent functionality.
Basically,
the concept here is that in the subjective world, the dichotomy between X and
not-X has a different sense than in objective reality. In objective reality (by which I mean “measurable
reality”, a la classical reality) we can’t have two alternative possibilities
both occur – at any particular point in time, the ball is either behind the
chair or not, and the rock is either hard or soft. On the other hand, in quantum reality the electron can pass
through both slit 1 and slit 2 (in the classic double-slit experiment). In subjective reality can for instance, one
really be both happy and unhappy at the same time, in the sense of mathematical
superposition?
There is a
trivial sense in which one can be both happy and unhappy at the same time: the
mind/brain is a large, complex system, and one part of it can be happy while
the other part is unhappy. But this is
not what I’m talking about; I’m proposing something more radically. The question I’m asking is whether it makes
sense to think of subjective states as unresolved superpositions among multiple
possibilities. If the answer is yes,
then this means one wants to use non-real probabilities to reason about
entities within subjective reality.
Which would be quite a major and exciting conclusion.
Note also
that merely concluding one should use non-real probabilities to model
subjective states doesn’t resolve the issue of what kinds of non-real
probabilities to use: complex, quaternionic, or octonionic. In the case of quantum reality the math only
works out so as to agree with experiment if one uses complex
probabilities. The situation with
subjective reality is far less clear to me at the moment.
My intuition
screams out at me here: Octonions!
Octonionic probabilities to measure the uncertainties of qualia! But I have nothing to substantiate this at
present, except for vague intuitions.
This is a train of thought I will definitely keep percolating in the
back of my mind, waiting for a breakthrough.
If one wants to show a role for octonions here, the key is to come up
with an argument why probabilities of subjective events would be nonassociative
… this would mean they have to be octonions rather than any of the other
possible algebraic entities.
Finally, let
me retreat from this particular train of thought for a moment and return to the
big picture. Whatever the fate of this
particular speculation about probabilities and subjectivity, it is an example
of the kind of possibility that arises when one takes subjective reality
seriously as a domain of being. I hope
I have made a good argument that this is worth doing, at least on a provisional
basis to see what comes out of it.